What philosophy, if any, is needed for cognitive science?

Philip V. Kargopoulos

Abstract


Abstract: The question posed in the title serves as a springboard to examine the interdisciplinary nature of cognitive science and the role philosophy should play. I will argue that philosophy has a clearly defined role to play over and above the contributions made by philosophies specific to the various disciplines engaged in cognitive science. I also point out that by engaging with cognitive science – an endeavor defined by a clear scientific goal – philosophy itself will have to change in ways that are bound to affect the future of philosophizing. In the first part of this paper, I play devil’s advocate, arguing that philosophy should not be amongst the disciplines engaged in cognitive science. In the second part, I discuss how the relationship between philosophy and psychology has been changed by their common participation in cognitive science: psychology is now admittedly philosophical and philosophy has become naturalized. In the third part, I suggest that philosophy is better equipped than psychology to handle the thorny question of representation in cognitive science. In the fourth part and conclusion, I argue that cognitive science will influence both the theory and practice of philosophy: the futures of cognitive science and philosophy are tied together.

Keywords: Philosophy; Cognitive Science; Cognitive Psychology; Naturalism; Epistemology

 

Quale filosofia – se una ce ne vuole – per la scienza cognitiva?

Riassunto: L’interrogativo posto nel titolo funge da punto di partenza per analizzare la natura interdisciplinare della scienza cognitiva e il ruolo che la filosofia dovrebbe avere al suo interno. Sosterrò che alla filosofia spetti un ruolo ben definito, al di là dei contributi forniti dai particolari indirizzi filosofici coinvolti nella scienza cognitiva. Sottolineerò anche che, confrontandosi con la scienza cognitiva – un ambito caratterizzato da un chiaro obiettivo scientifico – la filosofia stessa dovrà cambiare, assumendo modalità che influenzeranno il futuro del filosofare. Nella prima parte di questo articolo metterò le vesti dell’avvocato del diavolo, sostenendo come la filosofia non dovrebbe essere tra le discipline coinvolte nella scienza cognitiva. Nella seconda parte discuterò come il rapporto tra filosofia e psicologia sia mutato per effetto della comune partecipazione al progetto della scienza cognitiva: ora la psicologia è apertamente filosofica e la filosofia è filosofia naturalizzata. Nella terza parte mostrerò come la filosofia sia meglio equipaggiata della psicologia per fronteggiare l’ostico problema della rappresentazione nella scienza cognitiva. Nella quarta parte e nelle conclusioni sosterrò che la scienza cognitiva potrà influenzare la teoria e la pratica del filosofare: il futuro della scienza cognitiva e della filosofia sono reciprocamente legati. 

Parole chiave: Filosofia; Scienza cognitiva; Psicologia cognitiva; Naturalismo; Epistemologia


Parole chiave


Philosophy; Cognitive Science; Cognitive Psychology; Naturalism; Epistemology

Full Text

PDF

Riferimenti bibliografici


ARMSTRONG, S., GLEITMAN, L., GLEITMAN, N. (1983). What some concepts might not be. In: «Cognition», vol. XIII, n. 3, pp. 263-308.

BARSALOU, L.W. (1982). Context-independent and context-dependent information in concepts. In: «Memory and Cognition», vol. X, n. 1, pp. 82-93.

BARSALOU, L.W. (1983). Ad hoc categories. In: «Memory and Cognition», vol. XI, n. 3, pp. 211-227.

BARSALOU, L.W. (1987). The instability of graded structure: Implications for the nature of concepts. In: U. NEISSER (ed.), Concepts and conceptual development, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 101-140.

BROOKS, R.A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. In: «Artificial Intelligence», vol. XLVII, n. 1-3, pp. 139-159.

BROOKS, R.A. (2002). Flesh and machines, Vintage, New York.

BRUNER, J.S., GOODNOW, J.J., AUSTIN, G.A. (1956). A study of thinking, Wiley, New York.

CHALMERS, D. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. In: «Journal of Consciousness Studies», vol. II, n. 3, pp. 200-219.

CHALMERS, D. (1996). The conscious mind, Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York.

CHURCHLAND, P.M. (1995). The engine of reason the seat of the soul, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA).

DREYFUS, H. (1979). What computers can’t do (1972) Harper & Row, New York.

DREYFUS, H. (1992). What computers still can’t do, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA).

FODOR, J.A. (1973). The language of thought, MIT Pres, Cambridge (MA).

FODOR, J.A. (1983). The modularity of mind, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA).

FODOR, J.A. (2008). LOT 2, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

GARCIA, J., KOELING, R.A. (1966). Relation of cue to consequence in avoidance learning. In: «Psychonomic Science», vol. IV, n. 3, pp. 121-124.

GOODMAN, N. (1968). Languages of art, Bobbs and Merrill, New York.

GOODMAN, N. (1973). Problems and projects, Bobbs and Merrill, New York.

GOODMAN, N. (1978). Ways of worldmaking, Bobbs and Merrill, New York.

HARRIS, S., SCHETH, S.A., COHEN, M.S. (2008). Functional neuroimaging of belief, disbelief and uncertainty. In: «Annals of Neurology», vol. LXIII, pp. 141-147.

JACKSON, F. (1986). What Mary didn't know. In: «The Journal of Philosophy», vol. LXXXIII, n. 5, pp. 291-295.

KAHNEMAN, D. (1981). Who shall be the arbiter of our intuitions?. In: «Behavioral and Brain Sciences», vol. IV, n. 3, pp. 339-340.

KAHNEMAN, D., TVERSKY, A. (1972). Subjective probability: A judgment of representativeness. In: «Cognitive Psychology», vol. III, n. 3, pp. 430-454.

KAHNEMAN, D., TVERSKY, A. (1973). On the psychology of prediction. In: «Psychological Review», vol. LXXX, n. 4, pp. 237-251.

KOSSLYN, S.M. (1980). Image and mind, Harvard University Press, Cambridge (MA).

KOSSLYN, S.M., BALL, J.M., REISER, B.J. (1978). Visual images preserve metric spatial information. In: «Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception», vol. IV, n. 1, pp. 47-60.

LEVINE, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. In: «Pacific Philosophical Quarterly», vol. LXIV, n. 4, 1983, pp. 354-361.

LEVINE, J. (2001). Purple haze: The puzzle of consciousness, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

LIBET, B. (1965). Cortical activation in conscious and unconscious experience. In: «Perspectives in Biology and Medicine», vol. IX, n. 1, pp. 77-86.

LIBET, B. (2004). Mind time, Harvard University Press, Cambridge (MA).

LOFTUS, E. (1975). Leading questions and the eyewitness report. In: «Cognitive Psychology», vol. VII, n. 4, pp. 560-572.

LOGOTHETIS, N., SCHALL, J.D. (1989). Neuronal correlates of subjective visual perception. In: «Science», vol. CCXLV, n. 4919, pp. 761-763.

MACINTOSH, N.J. (1983). Conditioning and associative learning, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

MARKMAN, A.B. (1999). Knowledge representation, LEA, London.

MARR, D. (1982). Vision, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA).

MCCOON, R., RATCLIFF, G. (1979). Priming in episodic and semantic memory. In: «Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior», vol. XVIII, n. 4, pp. 463-480.

MCCOON, R., RATCLIFF, G. (1992). Spreading activation versus compound cue accounts of priming. In: «Journal of Experimental Psychology – Learning, Memory, and Cognition», vol. XVIII, n. 6, pp. 1155-1172.

MEDIN, D.L., SHAFFER, M.M. (1978). Context theory of classification learning. In: «Psychological Review», vol. LXXXV, n. 3, pp. 207-238.

MINSKY, M. (1987). The society of mind, Touchstone, New York.

NAGEL, T. (1974). What is it like to be a bat?. In: «Philosophical Review», vol. LXXXIII, n. 4, pp. 435-450.

OAKSFORD, M., CHATER, N. (2007). Bayesian rationality, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

OCCELLI, V. (2014). Molyneux’s question: A window on cross-modal interplay in blindness. In: «Rivista internazionale di Filosofia e di Psicologia», vol. V, n. 1, pp. 72-101.

POSNER, M.I., KEELE, S.W. (1968). On the genesis of abstract ideas. In: «Journal of Experimental Psychology», vol. LXXVII, n. 3, pp. 353-363.

PYLYSHYN, Z.W. (1973). What the mind’s eye tells the minds brain. In: «Psychological Bulletin», vol. LXXX, n. 1, pp. 1-24.

PYLYSHYN, Z.W. (1978). Imagery and artificial intelligence. In: C. SAVAGE (ed.), Perception and cognition, Minnesota University Press, Minneapolis, pp. 19-55.

PYLYSHYN, Z.W. (1981). The imagery debate. In: «Psychological Review», vol. LXXXVIII, n. 1, pp. 16-45.

QUINE, W.V.O. (1960). Word and object, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA).

QUINE, W.V.O. (1969). Ontological relativity and other essays, Columbia University Press, New York.

QUINE, W.V.O. (1974). The roots of reference, Open Court, La Salle.

REINVILLE, P., DUNCAN, G.M., PRICE, D.D., CARRIER, B., BUSHNELL, M.C. (1997). Pain affect encoded in human anterior cingulate but not somatosensory cortex. In: «Science», vol. CCLXXVII, n. 5328, pp. 968-971.

RESCORLA, R.A., SOLOMON, R.L. (1967). Two-process learning theory: Relationships between Pavlovian and instrumental learning. In: «Psychological Review», vol. LXXIV, n. 3, pp. 151-182.

ROSCH, E. (1978). Principles of categorization. In: E. ROSCH, B.B. LLOYD (eds.), Cognition and categorization, Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale (NJ), pp. 27-48.

RUSSELL, B. (1959). My philosophical development, Allen and Unwinn, London.

RYLE, G. (1949). The concept of mind, Hutchinson House, London.

SEARLE, J. (1980). Minds, brains and programs. In: «Behavioral and Brain Sciences», vol. III, n. 3, pp. 417-424.

SEARLE, J. (1990). Could a machine think?. In: «Scientific American», vol. CCLXII, n. 1, pp. 20-25.

SEARLE, J. (2002). Consciousness and language, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

SHEPARD, R.N. (1968). The mental image. In: «American Psychologist», vol. XXXIII, n. 2, pp. 125-137.

SHEPARD, R.N., COOPER, L.A. (1986). Mental images and their transformations, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA).

SKINNER, B.F. (1963). Behaviorism at fifty. In: «Science», vol. CXL, n. 3570, pp. 951-958.

SMITH CHURCHLAND, P. (1986). Neurophilosophy, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA).

SMITH CHURCHLAND, P. (2002). Brain-wise, MIT Press, Cambridge (MA).

SMITH CHURCHLAND, P., CHURCHLAND, P.M. (1990). Could a machine think?. In: «Scientific American», vol. CCLXII, n. 1, pp. 26-31.

SOWA, J.F. (2000). Knowledge representation: Logical, philosophical and computational foundations, Brooks and Cole, Boston.

TENGLAS, E., VUL, E., GIROTTO, V., GONZALEZ, M., TENEBAUM, J.B., BONATTI, L.L. (2011). Pure reasoning in 12-month-old infants as probabilistic inference. In: «Science», vol. CCCXXXII, n. 6033, pp. 1054-1059.

TOLMAN, E. (1948). Cognitive maps in rats and men. In: «Psychological Review», vol. LV, n. 4, pp. 189-208.

TURING, A.M. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. In: «Mind», vol. LIX, n. 236, pp. 433-460.

WITTGENSTEIN, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations, Routledge, London.




DOI: https://doi.org/10.4453/rifp.2023.0003

Copyright (c) 2023 Philip Kargopoulos

URLdella licenza: http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/

Rivista internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia - ISSN: 2039-4667 (print) - E-ISSN: 2239-2629 (online)

Registrazione al Tribunale di Milano n. 634 del 26-11-2010 - Direttore Responsabile: Aurelia Delfino

Web provider Aruba spa - Loc. Palazzetto, 4 - 52011 Bibbiena (AR) - P.IVA 01573850516 - C.F. e R.I./AR 04552920482

Licenza Creative Commons
Dove non diversamente specificato, i contenuti di Rivista Internazionale di Filosofia e Psicologia sono distribuiti con Licenza Creative Commons Attribuzione 4.0 Internazionale.